PET PET
  • My Account
  • Subscribe
Become a Friend Donate
  • About Us
    • People
    • Press Office
    • Our History
  • Get Involved
    • Become a Friend of PET
    • Volunteer
    • Campaigns
    • Writing Scheme
    • Partnership and Sponsorship
    • Advertise with Us
  • Donate
    • Become a Friend of PET
  • BioNews
    • News
    • Comment
    • Reviews
    • Elsewhere
    • Topics
    • Glossary
    • Newsletters
  • Events
    • Upcoming Events
    • Previous Events
  • Engagement
    • Policy and Projects
      • Resources
    • Education
  • Jobs & Opportunities
  • Contact Us
  • About Us
    • People
    • Press Office
    • Our History
  • Get Involved
    • Become a Friend of PET
    • Volunteer
    • Campaigns
    • Writing Scheme
    • Partnership and Sponsorship
    • Advertise with Us
  • Donate
    • Become a Friend of PET
  • BioNews
    • News
    • Comment
    • Reviews
    • Elsewhere
    • Topics
    • Glossary
    • Newsletters
  • Events
    • Upcoming Events
    • Previous Events
  • Engagement
    • Policy and Projects
      • Resources
    • Education
  • Jobs & Opportunities
  • Contact Us
  • My Account
  • Subscribe
  • Privacy Statement
  • Advertising Policy
  • Thanks and Acknowledgements
PETBioNewsCommentChoosing children: Reflections on the regulation of embryo testing

BioNews

Choosing children: Reflections on the regulation of embryo testing

Published 18 June 2009 posted in Comment and appears in BioNews 450

Author

Colin Gavaghan

Image by Peter Artymiuk via the Wellcome Collection. Depicts the shadow of a DNA double helix, on a background that shows the fluorescent banding of the output from a DNA sequencing machine.
CC BY 4.0
Image by Peter Artymiuk via the Wellcome Collection. Depicts the shadow of a DNA double helix, on a background that shows the fluorescent banding of the sequencing output from an automated DNA sequencing machine.

My remit for this piece starts with a request to 'reflect on the past nine years and beyond'. Coincidentally, it was about nine years ago that I made my own first tentative foray into publishing in the area of reproductive law and ethics, and it is a sobering thing to...

My remit for this piece starts with a request to 'reflect on the past nine years and beyond'. Coincidentally, it was about nine years ago that I made my own first tentative foray into publishing in the area of reproductive law and ethics, and it is a sobering thing to take stock of what has happened in the meantime.

The technology of PGD (preimplantation genetic diagnosis) - my own particular area of interest - has certainly moved on. It is now possible to test for over fifty different conditions, and demand is growing for tests for non-pathological traits such as sex and tissue type. The literature on the subject is also a lot richer; the last year or so has seen the publication of several books by British academics, looking wholly or largely at this technology, and offering a range of perspectives (1).


To what extent has this been reflected in the regulatory regime? The Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority (HFEA) has certainly adopted a somewhat lighter touch under more recent regimes. The volte face on tissue typing was welcome - if too late for the Whittaker family (2) - and its report 'Tomorrow's Children' (2005) was considerably more balanced and proportionate than previous approaches to the welfare of the child. 


The Government, alas, seems determined to move in the opposite direction. The new Human Fertilisation and Embryology Bill seems destined to make the rules regarding PGD even stricter, in both positive and negative ways - allowing PGD only for a limited number of reasons, and requiring certain implantation decisions to be made thereafter. In so doing, it fails utterly to engage with some of the most compelling ethical arguments.


Clause 14 (4) (9) requires that embryos known to have a significant risk of 'serious physical or mental disability' or 'serious illness must not be preferred to those that are not known to have such an abnormality'. There are at least two problems with this clause. The first relates to how we define 'serious disability' or 'abnormality'. This question has been at the heart of much of the recent debate about whether deaf parents should be allowed to choose to create a deaf child. Is deafness a 'serious disability'? Is it even a disability at all? Paragraph 110 of the Explanatory Notes to the Bill make it clear that, as far as this Clause is concerned, selection of embryos - or of gamete donors - for deafness would be prevented.


For some deaf people, this designation is decidedly problematic. As Tomato Lichy told The Observer recently (9/3/08): 'Being deaf is not about being disabled, or medically incomplete - it's about being part of a linguistic minority'. Even for those sceptical of the claim that deafness is not a disability at all, it may seem something of a stretch to classify it as a 'serious' disability, a term that, in this context, we might think more readily applicable to disastrous conditions like Tay Sachs disease.


These are arguments that merit serious consideration, but there is another objection to Clause 14 (4) (9) that has received rather less attention, an argument that does not rely on any particular view as to whether deafness is or is not a 'disability'. It relies, however, on a contention that appears highly counter-intuitive. Most people, it seems, share the sort of incomprehension expressed by John Humphrys during his interview with Mr Lichy on Radio 4's 'Today' programme, and espoused by Nicholas DeLacy-Brown in his BioNews commentary:  'the future child is owed a duty by which the most positive outcome is chosen by its parents.' (BioNews, 27 July 2007)


The problem with this kind of argument is that it relies on regarding 'the future child' as a single entity, rather than one of two possible future children who may come to exist. This is muddled thinking. Lichy and his partner Paula Garfield want to be able to implant a deaf embryo (more accurately, of course, an embryo that is likely to develop into a deaf child). If this is permitted, a deaf child will be born. If they are denied the choice, a hearing child will be born, but significantly, a different child will be born. For the deaf child, the possibility of 'life with hearing' was simply not on the table; the only alternative to life with deafness was no life at all.


Of course, it might be that certain kinds of disability are so dreadful that the lives affected by them are actually worse than non-existence. A deaf child will have no cause to complain to his parents, but maybe a child born with Tay-Sachs disease would actually have been better off never being born. If Clause 14 (4) (9) had limited itself to these plausibly worse-than-nothing lives, it could be said to rest on some coherent ethical principle. As it stands, it occupies the bizarre position of apparently seeking to protect future children from deafness by protecting them from existence; of safeguarding their interests by requiring their replacement with other, healthier children.


If potential parents want to select the 'healthiest' embryos, that choice should be respected; no harm is done to potential future people by deciding not to bring them into being. Equally, though, it is hard to see how any harm would result from the choice to implant a less healthy embryo, providing the resulting child has a subjectively worthwhile life. 


Certain - often quite ingenious - responses have been offered to this 'non-identity problem'. Jonathan Glover and John Harris have both espoused versions of non-person-affecting approaches to such questions. According to these, we should make choices that make the world a better rather than a worse place, even if no particular people would have been harmed by the alternative choices. 


But if we have an obligation to contribute to the collective pot of human happiness by having the 'best possible children', what does this say about those who chose to have no children at all? It seems a bit like saying that, while we have no obligation to give anything to charity, those who contribute a bit are duty-bound to contribute as much as possible. For that reason, and others, my own preference is to say that our moral duties extend to those people who actually exist, or who will exist in the future. Nonetheless, there is some substance to these non-person-affecting views, and this is a perspective worth taking seriously.


The Government, alas, seems to have felt no need to give such an account of its reasons. Intuitive revulsion at the prospect of 'designer babies' and elective disability seems to have informed the new Bill far more than considered ethical argument. It is disappointing to reflect that in the nine years since BioNews commenced, and I became involved in this area, so much intellectual effort has been expended by so many people to such apparently little effect.


Related Articles

Image by Alan Handyside via the Wellcome Collection. Depicts a human egg soon after fertilisation, with the two parental pronuclei clearly visible.
CC0 1.0
Image by Alan Handyside via the Wellcome Collection. Depicts a human egg soon after fertilisation, with the two parental pronuclei clearly visible.
News
1 September 2009 • 2 minutes read

British couples can choose baby's sex in US clinic

by Sarah Pritchard

A fertility clinic in the USA has revealed that it provides sex selection to many British couples who pay large amounts of money to travel and receive the service....

Image by Peter Artymiuk via the Wellcome Collection. Depicts the shadow of a DNA double helix, on a background that shows the fluorescent banding of the output from a DNA sequencing machine.
CC BY 4.0
Image by Peter Artymiuk via the Wellcome Collection. Depicts the shadow of a DNA double helix, on a background that shows the fluorescent banding of the sequencing output from an automated DNA sequencing machine.
Comment
18 June 2009 • 5 minutes read

Debating deafness and embryo selection: Are we undermining reproductive confidence in the deaf community?

by Ailsa Stevens

Clause 14 of the Human Fertilisation and Embryology Bill states that in assisted reproduction, embryos known to be at risk of developing 'serious physical or mental disability' or 'serious illness' must not be preferred to embryos where there is no such risk (1). In the official Explanatory Notes to the...

Image by Peter Artymiuk via the Wellcome Collection. Depicts the shadow of a DNA double helix, on a background that shows the fluorescent banding of the output from a DNA sequencing machine.
CC BY 4.0
Image by Peter Artymiuk via the Wellcome Collection. Depicts the shadow of a DNA double helix, on a background that shows the fluorescent banding of the sequencing output from an automated DNA sequencing machine.
News
9 June 2009 • 2 minutes read

New embryo test could detect thousands of hereditary disorders

by Dr Rebecca Robey

UK scientists have developed a new screening technique that could allow prospective parents to test their IVF embryos for any known genetic disease. The test, dubbed 'a genetic MoT', would cost just £1500 and could be available by next year pending licensing by the Human Fertilisation and...

Image by Peter Artymiuk via the Wellcome Collection. Depicts the shadow of a DNA double helix, on a background that shows the fluorescent banding of the output from a DNA sequencing machine.
CC BY 4.0
Image by Peter Artymiuk via the Wellcome Collection. Depicts the shadow of a DNA double helix, on a background that shows the fluorescent banding of the sequencing output from an automated DNA sequencing machine.
News
9 June 2009 • 2 minutes read

Parents should be allowed to transfer affected embryos, say ethicists

by Ailsa Stevens

BioNews reporting from ESHRE conference, Barcelona:By Ailsa Taylor: Amidst current debate about the implications of allowing couples to select embryos free from conditions with later onset, incomplete penetrance and (limited) treatment options, ethicists have recommended that parents undergoing pre-implantation genetic diagnosis (PGD) should, in certain circumstances, be allowed to...

Leave a Reply Cancel reply

You must be logged in to post a comment.

« Artificial Gametes: The What, Why and How of Creating Sperm and Eggs in the Lab

Data-Label The UK's Leading Supplier Of Medical Labels & Asset Labels

RetiringDentist.co.uk The UK's Leading M&A Company.
easyfundraising
amazon

This month in BioNews

  • Recent
4 July 2022 • 4 minutes read

Widening the debate about direct-to-consumer genetic testing and donor conception

4 July 2022 • 3 minutes read

Join PET and Genomics England to celebrate the 200th birthday of Gregor Mendel

27 June 2022 • 4 minutes read

Thirty years of PET: our 'Fertility, Genomics and Embryo Research' report

27 June 2022 • 5 minutes read

Children's rights and donor conception: What next?

20 June 2022 • 4 minutes read

The problems with lifting donor anonymity earlier

Subscribe to BioNews and other PET updates for free.

Subscribe
  • Twitter
  • Facebook
  • Instagram
  • LinkedIn
  • YouTube
  • RSS
Wellcome
Website redevelopment supported by Wellcome.

Website by Impact Media Impact Media

  • Privacy Statement
  • Advertising Policy
  • Thanks and Acknowledgements

© 1992 - 2022 Progress Educational Trust. All rights reserved.

Limited company registered in England and Wales no 07405980 • Registered charity no 1139856

Subscribe to BioNews and other PET updates for free.

Subscribe
PET PET

PET is an independent charity that improves choices for people affected by infertility and genetic conditions.

  • Twitter
  • Facebook
  • Instagram
  • LinkedIn
  • YouTube
  • RSS
Wellcome
Website redevelopment supported by Wellcome.

Navigation

  • About Us
  • Get Involved
  • Donate
  • BioNews
  • Events
  • Engagement
  • Jobs & Opportunities
  • Contact Us

BioNews

  • News
  • Comment
  • Reviews
  • Elsewhere
  • Topics
  • Glossary
  • Newsletters

Other

  • My Account
  • Subscribe

Website by Impact Media Impact Media

  • Privacy Statement
  • Advertising Policy
  • Thanks and Acknowledgements

© 1992 - 2022 Progress Educational Trust. All rights reserved.

Limited company registered in England and Wales no 07405980 • Registered charity no 1139856